Heidegger On Ontology And Mass Communication.pdf

(152 KB) Pobierz
Idle Talk: Ontology and Mass Communications in Heidegger
I DLE T ALK : O NTOLOGY AND M ASS
C OMMUNICATIONS IN H EIDEGGER
David Dwan
In Human all too Human Nietzsche outlined the philosophical challenge
presented by modern media systems. ‘The press, the machine, the railway,
the telegraph’, he opined, ‘are premises whose thousand-year conclusion
no one has yet dared to draw’. 1 All of these objects constitute a media circuit
which challenge old certainties about community, communication and
subjectivity. While others might have failed to syllogise upon the premises
of the press, Nietzsche did not hesitate to draw his own conclusions about
the brave new world of journalism. ‘Just look at these superfluous people’,
shouts Zarathustra, ‘they vomit their bile and call it a newspaper. They devour
one another and cannot even digest themselves’. 2 A similar rage appears
later in Zarathustra : ‘Do you not see the souls hanging like dirty, limp rags?
- And they also make newspapers from these rags!’ Under the influence of
newspapers, spirit has become ‘a repulsive verbal swill’ (196). In the Gay
Science , Nietzsche also equated journalism with the ‘prostitution of the spirit’. 3
This degeneracy of the spirit he also condemns in Beyond Good and Evil ,
when he focuses on ‘the newspaper-reading demi-monde of the spirit’. 4 Here
he also presents ‘parliamentary imbecility, including the obligation upon
everyone to read his newspaper at breakfast’, as examples of European
nihilism (138). In Human all too Human he sadly surveys ‘the press as it is
now, with its daily expenditure of lungpower on exclaiming, deafening,
inciting, shocking - is it anything more than the permanent false alarm that
leads ears and senses off in the wrong direction?’(287).
One might view Nietzsche’s anti-journalistic polemic as a set of local
prejudices that remain marginal to a more properly philosophical enterprise.
Nevertheless, the newspaper acts as a key metaphor in Nietzsche’s texts,
sustaining a series of substantial - if implicit - claims about the constitution
of subjectivity. Nietzsche suggests that newspapers remove the conditions
for authentic subjectivity, although it is a matter of some doubt whether any
subject which requires conditions anterior or extrinsic to itself is not already
doomed to heteronomy and inauthenticity in Nietzsche’s eyes. In criticising
newspapers, Nietzsche criticises a vulgar, expressive subject who requires
affirmation in the eyes of others. The clichéd vocabularies of ‘spirit’ in which
this expressivity is couched merely confirms a subjective lack; self-expression
is akin to vomit, while the hackneyed effusions of the expressive ‘soul’ merely
confirm the latter’s absence. Here the verbose self is comparable to ‘dirty
limp rags’; it is a radically heteronymous creature as fragmented as it is
soiled and second-hand. Those who consume such vomit also effect a turn
1. Nietzsche, Human
all too Human
( HTH) , R.J.
Hollingdale (trans),
Richard Schacht
(introd), Cambridge,
Cambridge
University Press,
1996, p378.
2. Friedrich
Nietzsche, Thus
Spoke Zarathustra
( TSZ ), R.J.
Hollingdale (trans),
London, Penguin,
1961, p77.
3. Friedrich
Nietzsche, The Gay
Science ( TGS ), Walter
Kaufmann (trans),
New York, Vintage,
1974, p103.
4. Friedrich
Nietzsche, Beyond
Good and Evil
( BG&E ), R.J.
Hollingdale (trans),
Michael Tanner
(introd), London,
Penguin, 1990,
p203.
I DLE T ALK 113
566216663.001.png
5. Martin Heidegger,
Nietzsche IV: Nihilism
( NIV ), David Farrell
Krell (ed), Joan
Stambaugh, David
Farrell Krell and
Frank A. Capuzzi
(trans), New York,
Harper & Row,
1982, p47.
from the self; they hungrily devour others but ‘cannot digest themselves’.
Newspapers, it would appear, constitute a network of heteronomy and
preside over a collective abdication of the self. Whatever the truth of these
comments, Nietzsche helped to introduce the newspaper as an object for
truth or philosophical reflection. In the genre of philosophy, Nietzsche
installs the newspaper as the basis of the philosophical aside, which is only
superficially viewed as an aside to philosophy.
Martin Heidegger takes his cue from Nietzsche in his use of a
philosophical vocabulary within which the newspaper features as a significant
metaphor. Indeed, in his lectures on Nietzsche Heidegger cites with approval
his precursor’s critique of a media-saturated age: ‘Around the year 1882 he
says regarding his times, ‘‘Our age is an agitated one, and precisely for this
reason, not an age of passion; it heats itself up continuously, because it feels
that it is not warm - basically it is freezing … In our time it is merely by
means of an echo that events acquire their ‘greatness’ - the echo of the
newspaper.”’ 5 Heidegger’s advocacy of Nietzsche’s anti-journalistic polemic
may seem relatively insignificant. His pronouncements on the press mark
perhaps a momentary abandonment of philosophical high seriousness and
should be interpreted in that spirit. Or we might conclude that the thorough
banality of these views removes any basis for a critical engagement with
them. According to Jürgen Habermas, ‘Heidegger’s critical judgements …
on the dictatorship of the public realm and the impotence of the private
sphere, on technocracy and mass civilisation, are without any originality
whatsoever because they belong to a repertoire of opinions typical of a certain
generation of German mandarins’. 6
Heidegger’s pronouncements about mass communications are, it seems,
banal in themselves and partake in the very idle talk he professes to despise.
However, I want to argue that when his local criticisms of media systems are
related to his philosophy as a whole, they succeed in raising some
fundamental questions about the nature and coherence of that enterprise.
Thus, while this essay is primarily concerned with Heidegger’s ontology
(and its engagement with mass communications largely incidental to this
more general concern), the decision to use Heidegger’s views on modern
media systems as an interpretative avenue into his philosophy is not an
arbitrary one. Heidegger’s pronouncements about mass communications
(and technology in general) reflect his wider commitment to being a
philosopher of our public life. According to his student, Hans-Georg
Gadamer, Heidegger radically overhauled academic philosophy after the
war; he challenged its position of disengaged transcendence and succeeded
in rendering philosophy meaningful to a disillu sioned generation. 7
Philosophy, it seemed, could once again contribute to the practical task of
living and could attempt solutions or, at the very least, lend a determination
to problems common to us all. The ‘problem of technology’, in particular,
exercised Heidegger and his entire generation. Moreover, he was intensely
concerned about the way technology, through the aegis of media systems,
6. Jürgen Habermas,
The Philosophical
Discourse of Modernity
( PDOM ), Frederick
Lawrence (trans),
Cambridge, Polity
Press, 1987, p140.
7. Hans-Georg
Gadamer,
Philosophical
Hermeneutics ( PH ),
David E. Linge
(trans and ed),
Berkeley, Los
Angeles and
London, University
of California Press,
pp229-230.
114 N EW F ORMATIONS
encroached upon our everyday speech-environments. In Heidegger’s eyes
technologies such as radios and newspapers distorted social interaction and
damaged the communicative tissue of our world. He had considerable
difficulty, however, in identifying with any precision the nature of this damage
or the agencies through which it might be addressed.
As we shall see in the course of this essay, Heidegger produces different
and often incompatible views of mass media throughout his career. These
shifting and contradictory attitudes record transitions in his overall thought.
They also reflect, I shall argue, Heidegger’s broader difficulty in lending
his ontology a critical function or a normative dimension. Not only does
Heidegger’s personal commitment to philosophy’s public vocation demand
this engagement, but it is a logical requirement of his own published
philosophical views. If Dasein is always concern-fully absorbed in its world,
if care is a primordial attitude from which all other dispositions derive,
then philosophy cannot coherently exempt itself from this attitude of care.
How we care about media systems, therefore, raises questions not simply
about the application of a philosophy to everyday life-issues, but also the
logical consistency of this philosophy. Heidegger’s difficulty in responding
to the problem of media systems or even identifying what kind of problem
it constitutes, reflects, I shall argue, a more general ambiguity in his work
concerning the status of problems as such. We shall explore the conceptual
nature of this difficulty in some detail later in the essay, but we can begin to
sketch out its lineaments by considering the rival interpretations he offers
of mass media in the modern world.
Heidegger arrived at two diametrically opposed accounts of the ‘problem’
of media systems. The first view, which he adopted in Being and Time , presents
newspapers and radios as symptoms of das Man or what is often translated
as ‘the they’. These technologies constitute a media circuit which connives
against identity. This circuit is neither a subject nor an object, but is a sort
of black hole in which these predicates lose all meaning. Oswald Spengler
described the press as ‘a monstrous intellectual Something’ and Heidegger’s
das Man is characterised by an equally sublime anonymity. 8 As the medium
in which das Man moves, newspapers are a site of indeterminacy and a radical
dispersal of meaning. This is inauthentic being. Many commentators have
disputed whether inauthenticity operates as a descriptive or normative
category, but since Heidegger challenges this very distinction in Being and
Time , it seems contrary to the spirit of the work to re-install it here. Within
this context Heidegger strikes a distinctly Nietzschean pose. Authenticity
can only be reclaimed when Dasein rescues itself from this anonymous verbal
drift and grounds itself as a self-determining and self-accountable entity.
Authentic Dasein distinguishes itself thereby from those newspaper readers,
who, as Nietzsche put it, cannot ‘digest themselves’. Heidegger returned to
this point in a later lecture and insisted that the ‘superman’s appearance is
. . . inaccessible to the teletypers and radios dispatches of the press’. 9
But Heidegger was also one of Nietzsche’s most formidable critics. Not
8. Oswald Spengler,
The Decline of the
West , Vol. II:
Perspectives of World-
History ( DOTW ),
Charles Francis
Atkinson (trans) ,
London, Allen &
Unwin Ltd., 1928,
p460.
9. Martin Heidegger,
What is Called
Thinking ? ( WICT ),
F.D. Wieck and J.
Glenn Gray (trans),
New York, Evanston,
and London, Harper
& Row, 1968, p72.
I DLE T ALK 115
only did he distance himself from Nietzsche, but he also produced alongside
this critique an assessment of media systems, which, although equally
scathing, was wholly at odds with his earlier views. If newspapers produce
the catastrophe of subjectivity and objectivity in Being and Time they constitute
their highest apotheosis and greatest triumph in Heidegger’s later work.
Newspapers, in other words, collude with the modern subject in its ruthless
objectification of the world – that is the reduction of the world to the status
of brute objecthood. To understand this claim, we need to contextualise
Heidegger’s later views on newspapers within his wider assessment of
modernity. ‘The period we call modern’, according to Heidegger, ‘is defined
by the fact that man becomes the centre and measure of all being. Man is
the subiectum , that which lies at the bottom of all beings, that is, in modern
terms at the bottom of all objectification and representation’( NIV 28).
Nietzsche, according to Heidegger, stands within this tradition as modernity’s
greatest and last metaphysician. Heidegger concedes that Nietzsche is one
of the most skilled critics of the metaphysics of subjectivism - a tradition
which predicates a subject and an object as the generative basis for its own
conversations. Nietzsche criticised subjectivism’s commitment to moral and
epistemological certainty, insisting that the will to certainty impedes the
will to power. He repudiated its model of truth convinced that the
hypostatisation of being as presence forecloses all possibilities of becoming.
But Heidegger remains convinced that Nietzsche’s critique is ultimately
conducted in the name of a higher-order subjectivity - a subjectivity that no
longer requires such metaphysical ballast in order to sustain itself. According
to Heidegger, the category of the subject is an illusion that presides over
the real domination of the earth. He does not offer modifications of the
subject; he does not choose to emphasise the more significant modalities of
subjectivity to which subjectivism, itself is blind, but aspires to exceed the
metaphysics of subjectivism tout court.
Now while Nietzsche presented newspapers as the antithesis of authentic
subjectivity and Heidegger tended to adopt a similar view in Being and Time ,
the later Heidegger often presents media systems as wholly complicit with
the metaphysics of subjectivism. If the ‘absolute objectification of … being
as such results from the self-fulfilling dominion of subjectivity’ then
newspapers extend this dominion ( NIV 242). As Heidegger put it in his
Nietzsche lectures, ‘“journalism” identifies the metaphysical securing and
establishment of the everydayness of our dawning age … through which
everyone is provided with the ever-useful objectivities of the day. At the
same time, it reflects the self-completing objectification of beings as a whole’
( NIV 241). Heidegger, in other words, enlists newspapers in his general
account of modernity as the reign of the Ge-Stell - a subjectivist ordering of
the world. Under the dominion of the Ge-Stell only those items which affirm
the subject’s pre-conceived categories and purposes are admitted to the
order of representation over which newspapers preside. Oswald Spengler
had already outlined the way newspapers ‘determine “the truth”’, insisting
116 N EW F ORMATIONS
that what it obtains is ‘just its truth ’; the later Heidegger adopts a similar
view but insists that the ‘truth’ of the newspaper is also the ‘truth’ of a
subjectivist metaphysics ( DOTW 461). By reducing truth to representation
newspapers collude in the positivistic reduction of the world to the present-
at-hand. The world is presented as an object prior to and independent of
language, in a way that depletes the world of its history and blinds us to the
world-disclosive properties of language. Language now becomes a simple
tool or a useful mediator between two ‘objective’ or present-at-hand entities.
The subject wields a tool-like language and fails to consider how the subject
is the instrument of language itself. Newspapers intensify this reification of
language and prepare the way for the conquest of the world as picture.
Congealed thus into an object from which the subject stands removed, the
world loses its history and historically variegated aspect:
Everything is levelled to one level. Our minds hold views on all and
everything, and view all things in the identical way. Today every
newspaper, every illustrated magazine, and every radio program offers
all things in the identical way to uniform views … The one-sided view…
has puffed itself up into an all-sidedness which in turn is masked so as to
look harmless and natural. But this all-sided view which deals in all and
everything with equal uniformity and mindlessness … reduces everything
to a univocity of concepts and specifications the precision of which not
only corresponds to, but has the same essential origin as, the precision
of technological process ( WISCT 33-34)
While the Heidegger of Being and Time had emphasised the indeterminacy
and vagueness of media, he now emphasises its ‘precision’ - the ‘precision
of technological process’. Mass communications are part of an expansive
industrial circuit which begins with the forester who produces the raw product
for paper and ends with ‘newspapers and illustrated magazines’. The latter,
according to Heidegger ‘set public opinion to swallowing what is printed,
so that a set configuration of opinion becomes available on demand’. 10
Communicative interaction is now hypostatised to the level of object for the
purposes of mass consumption. According to Heidegger, modern cybernetics
typifies this kind of objectification. ‘Cybernetics’, as he put it, ‘transforms
language into an exchange of news. The arts become regulated-regulating
instruments of information’. 11 The notion of language, congealed into an
object and reduced to its function was already implicit in the concept of
‘information’ for some time. Walter Benjamin, for instance, noted a similar
reification of language, in his account of the decline of storytelling in an
age of information. 12 Heidegger suggests that information systems such as
newsp apers pre side over what he iden tified as the ‘epoch of the
unconditioned and complete objectification of everything that is’, which
begins with the ‘self-fulfilling metaphysics of subjectivity’( NIV 241).
Heidegger thus reduces the premises of the press, which Nietzsche had
10. Martin
Heidegger, The
Question Concerning
Technology and Other
Essays ( QCT ), New
York, Harper & Row,
1977, p18.
11. Martin
Heidegger, Basic
Writings ( BW ), David
Farrell Krell (ed),
revised edition,
London, Routledge,
1993, p434.
12. Walter Benjamin,
‘The Storyteller’, in
Illuminations ,
Hannah Arendt (ed.
and introd), Harry
Zohn (trans), New
York, Harcourt
Brace and World,
1968, pp83-107.
I DLE T ALK 117
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin