REPRESENTATION OF NATURE IN buddhist and western art.pdf

(124 KB) Pobierz
660479263 UNPDF
LANDSCAPE AESTHETICS AND
ENVIRONMENTALISM: SOME
OBSERVATIONS ON THE
REPRESENTATION OF NATURE IN
BUDDHIST AND WESTERN ART 1
Ian Harris
Introductory remarks
The word ‘nature’ is one of the most multi-dimensional terms in the English
language. It seems that the same may also be said in other culture contexts, such
as Japan where the term shizen clearly has the same extensive semantic range
(Asquith and Kalland 1997, 8). This fact poses one of the major difficulties in
examining the environmentalist credentials of Buddhism. But there are others, for
when we turn to that tradition itself we are confronted by an enormously complex
phenomenon, in both the historical, cultural and the geographical senses. These
facts imply that, in order to make any helpful contribution to this investigation, it is
necessary to limit the scope of one’s investigations. To do otherwise would be to
open oneself to immense and vacuous generalization.
The customary approach, one that I have used myself on previous
occasions, is to restrict oneself to a narrow segment of scriptural sources, be
they Therav ¯ da, Mah ¯ y ¯ na or Vajray ¯ na, in an effort to establish or refute the
environmentalist credentials of the Buddhist tradition as a whole. 2 But the
method suffers a number of methodological difficulties, the most obvious of
which is that a great deal of abstraction is inevitable in the way in which specific
literary references are selected. In addition, the passages are often presented with
no real account of the context in which they were produced. Indeed, we often
know too little about this, particularly when dealing with materials from
Buddhism’s formative centuries.
For the purposes of this paper I intend to adopt a slightly different
approach. Let us first deal with the Western term ‘nature’, which I shall define as
‘the totality of all existents’. This most comprehensive of all categories may be
broken down into two reasonably discrete components, namely the animate and
Contemporary Buddhism, Vol. 8, No. 2, November 2007
ISSN 1463-9947 print/1476-7953 online/07/020149-168
q 2007 Taylor & Francis DOI: 10.1080/14639940701636125
660479263.001.png
150 IAN HARRIS
inanimate realms, which correspond very closely with two key and well-attested
Buddhist categories—sattvaloka, the world of sentient beings; and bh¯ janaloka,
the receptacle, physical environment, or landscape in which sentient beings find
themselves as a result of their past actions.
It is my contention that the Buddhist tradition as a whole has a good deal of
very positive things to say about our relations with other beings in sattvaloka and
that much of this is supportive of modern environmentalist ethics. Deleanu’s
(2000) important study of the ethology of the P¯ li Canon, for example, appears to
bear this out. But when we turn our attention to the Buddhist appreciation of the
structure and significance of the physical stage on which humans, animals and
supernatural beings are located, the evidence is more equivocal. It is for this
reason that I shall now intend to restrict our discussion to bh¯ janaloka, and more
specifically to the mountains, forests, rivers that make up our natural landscape.
Accordingly, I propose to take the aesthetic dimensions of selected portions
of the Buddhist tradition, and particularly how far we can talk of an aesthetic
appreciation of the natural world, as the focus of this presentation. The issue has a
major bearing on the way in which we might regard the natural world as having
some sort of intrinsic significance or value quite apart from the ways in which it
can be utilized to the advantage of humankind. I also hope that the approach will
be a modest contribution towards redressing the balance in the customary
approach to Buddhist studies that to my mind has tended to devalue the visual
sense in favour of an emphasis on the intellectual elements. Clearly, if we
appreciate something we tend to accord it importance and are loath to see it
damaged or destroyed. This insight has played an important role in the fashioning
of modern environmentalism, and the emergence of an aesthetic appreciation of
nature in European culture was a major contributory factor in the construction of
our current preoccupation with the deteriorating state of the world.
I will briefly sketch out the main historical arteries of the Western aesthetic
appreciation of nature before examining how far they may be transposed on
specific forms of historical Buddhism. For the purposes of this paper I will contrast
the aesthetics of Indian and Sino-Japanese Buddhism and ask how far their artistic
traditions illuminate the way in which they came to represent the receptacle world
(bh¯ janaloka). If we are able to demonstrate that evidence of authentic Buddhist
appreciations of the natural world, then we are in a good position to posit the
tradition’s positive environmentalist credentials. If, on the other hand, this
condition cannot be met, then it may be the case that the forms of Buddhism
under consideration do not meet the criteria often claimed of them by their
supporters both in Asia and in the West, where ‘green orientalism’ (Asquith and
Kalland 1997, 25) has risen to prominence over the past couple of decades.
Nature in Western art
In the beginning, Western aesthetics concerned itself largely with questions
relating to the beauty of human artefacts. With the exception of precious stones
LANDSCAPE AESTHETICS AND ENVIRONMENTALISM 151
and other fascinating light-reflecting objects that required some form of human
agency to uncover their attractions, the natural world was not worthy of aesthetic
consideration since it was not thought of as the product of a designing
intelligence. Unlike art, then, the natural realm could not be easily appreciated.
And in any case, Western philosophy was strongly influenced by a Christian
theology that held the structure of nature to reflect man’s fallen state (Coates
1998, 131). When nature was thought of in aesthetic terms at all, the best that
could be said was that its beauty was tainted by mundaneity. As such it manifested
a pale resemblance of the glory invested by God in his original creation (Crawford
2005, 312).
Given this background it is unsurprising that the English poet and politician
Andrew Marvell (1621 – 1678) described mountains as ‘ill-designed excrescences’
since he had been conditioned by his intellectual tradition to view them in
opposition to the smooth fertile plains of creation in its original state. Similarly,
Thomas Burnet in his influential The Sacred Theory of the Earth of 1684 claimed that
the earth was originally as smooth as an egg. Its mountains and wilderness areas
were post-diluvian junk resulting from human sin and deposited on the surface of
the world following mankind’s expulsion from paradise.
In 1757 Edmund Burke published A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of
Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful, a book in which he built on the prior
aesthetical ruminations of John Evelyn (1620 – 1706), Joseph Addison (1672 – 1719)
and Anthony Ashley Cooper, third Earl of Shaftesbury (1671 – 1713), who had
waxed lyrical over the superiority of natural over artificial beauty. The importance
of Burke’s book is that he argued for the existence of the sublime, an artistic effect
that produced the strongest emotions the human mind was capable of
experiencing. But it was left to Immanuel Kant (1724 – 1804) to develop the
implications of this new theory by establishing an explicit distinction between the
merely beautiful and the sublime. In the Critique of Judgement in 1790, Kant noted
that a true experience of the sublime emerges when an observer is confronted
by an overwhelmingly impressive object. A good example would be a mighty
mountain. As one struggles to comprehend such a massive perception the
intellect is led inevitably towards the idea of infinity, and this mental process
in turn makes one conscious of the superiority of one’s rational being over all
sensible limitations. This feeling is intensified when we apprehend a vast and
potentially dangerous natural phenomenon with a disinterested attitude and from
a point of safety, for example through the window of our study. By contemplating
its power to make us fearful and highly vulnerable we are mysteriously elevated
above the purely natural and experience a sense of the sublime.
There are potential Buddhist parallels here, for P ¯ li sources suggest that an
experience of fear (samvega) and other powerful emotions may stimulate a sense of
moral and religious urgency in the religious practitioner. In this connection, Heim
(2003, 546, 549) has argued for some form of semantic overlap with the Kantian
sublime in the sense that, from the Buddhist perspective, our fears and anxieties,
152 IAN HARRIS
elicited for example by contemplation of the awesome nature of a bodhisattva’s
extraordinary deeds, may prompt us to reach out for ‘something great’.
Kant’s thoughts were, in time, to impact on Arthur Schopenhauer (1788 –
1860), a highly significant figure in the emerging European appreciation of
Buddhism, who built upon the idea of the sublime through his insistence that
aesthetic appreciation (he was primarily interested in our experience of music)
involved an act of will-less, or disinterested, contemplation. Schopenhauer
subsequently recommended the careful consideration of various phenomena
associated with the natural world such as waterfalls, the structure of crystals, and
magnetism. This attitude towards the sublime can be traced in the poetry of
Wordsworth and Coleridge, while in America it became an important stimulus
for the American transcendentalists—especially in the writings of Ralph Waldo
Emerson (1803 – 1882) and Henry David Thoreau (1817 – 1862), two further figures
in the transmission of knowledge about Buddhism to the West who also both
played seminal roles in the development of modern environmentalist philosophy.
Back in Europe the Romantic movement built on the idea of the sublime to
underpin a new kind of appreciation of natural or scenic beauty in the fine arts,
and most especially in painting. John Ruskin (1819 – 1900), for example, wrote of
how he deplored the manner in which painters of previous epochs had
approached the representation of nature (Coates 1998, 131). While classical and
medieval artists had certainly included elements of the natural world in their work,
they tended to use these either as a frame for human activity or as a means of
expressing human moods. Ruskin also complained that, on the odd occasions
when nature had been more explicitly represented, the dominant character of the
painting was pastoral. This attitude clearly changes in the late eighteenth and
early nineteenth centuries, as Philip de Loutherbourg’s An Avalanche in the Alps of
1803 demonstrates. For here the vastness of a natural realm indifferent to and
uncontaminated by human concerns picks up on the newly dominant cultural
notion of the sublime.
It is at this point in Western cultural history that even the most threatening
and traditionally despised of nature’s manifestations, like mountains and the
wilderness, begin to be positively and disinterestedly appreciated without any
negative feelings of anxiety or fear. It is against this background that we should
understand the emergence of a positive landscape aesthetics associated with the
Essay on Prints of 1768 by the Anglican divine William Gilpin (1724 – 1804), who
first introduced the world to the concept of the picturesque, an ‘agreeable’ and
essentially safe aesthetic quality associated with the painted English landscapes
that were becoming fashionable at his time. And somewhat later, Henry David
Thoreau (1817 – 1862) and the naturalist and founder of the influential Sierra Club
John Muir (1838 – 1914), whose writings emphasized both the awesome beauty of
the wilderness and the strong intuition that this realm is under potential threat
from the kinds of human activity initiated by the industrial revolution.
Yet the industrial revolution itself led to the development of entirely novel
forms of mass communication, especially the railways, and these would gradually
LANDSCAPE AESTHETICS AND ENVIRONMENTALISM 153
transform the notion of the sublime. In due course the largely solitary and
aristocratic ideal of confronting nature’s grandeur was democratized by modern
tourism. Gilpin’s ideas both anticipated and made possible the transformation. But
nature’s awe-inducing character was somehow domesticated. Its vast canvas was,
so to speak, cut up into a series of ‘prospects’ or blocks of scenery (Carlson 2001,
159f). Under these new conditions the typical Sunday afternoon trip to the country
became a little like a trip around an art gallery looking at a variety of landscape
paintings. In other words, the disinterested attitude that had paved the way for
the emergence of the sublime slowly migrated towards the picturesque.
The term ‘picturesque’ implies an appreciation of nature understood as a
series of ‘picture-like’ compositions influenced by highly subjective and emotional
moods that render its objective reality in a variety of appealing art styles.
It emerged as the result of changing economic circumstances, in particular the
development of cheap travel by railway that in turn democratized access to the
countryside. But in contrast to pre-industrial times when an individual’s existence
was embedded in the rural setting, now one could visit the countryside to
appreciate its beauty, spirituality and health-giving qualities. The picturesque was
to greatly influence the aesthetics of tourism, and it still provides a basis for the
illustrations for contemporary travel brochures, postcards and calendars not just in
Europe and America but in all economically developed regions of the world.
I contend that the picturesque was to become one of the major
contributory factors to the emergence of an environmentalist vision of the world.
But contemporary thinking is also strongly pervaded by the scientific spirit. In the
past, long before the rise of globalization, humans had distinctly limited
opportunities for travel and most never passed beyond the boundaries of their
own locality. As such they tended to regard themselves as part of a local field of
significance and had no real notion of the concept of an environment understood
in the scientific sense. What I mean here is that previous generations had no
conception of the extensive and objective realm determined by general
mechanistic processes known to science as ‘nature’. Such a vision would have
made no sense when subjective attitudes, emotions and imagination played such
an important role in our understanding of the world. But as Cooper (1992, 171) has
observed, ecology is ‘ ... as much of a leveller as any other physical science’. It has
tended to reinforce a picture of the world governed by uniform laws and devoid
of local colour and significance. Ironically, environmental ethicists have often
complained about the consequences of this worldview, but, for our present
purposes, it is now necessary to evaluate how significantly Buddhist conceptions
of the natural world share the same semantic territory as the sublime, the
picturesque and the scientistic conception of nature.
Indic attitudes towards the natural realm
In 1990 the Dalai Lama was invited to address a conference on the topic of
‘Spirit and Nature’. But he seems to have disappointed his American audience by
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin