Elsevier Science International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences Vol. T-Z.pdf
(
11630 KB
)
Pobierz
649893897 UNPDF
T
Taboo
vi-Strauss argued
that the incest taboo generates inter-familial relations,
providing the basis for the exchange of women (or
marriage partners of either sex) that in effect consti-
tutes society. Whereas Freud in
Totem and Taboo
emphasized the temporal significance of the incest
taboo (whose phylogenetic origin in actual historical
events is largely dismissed by anthropologists) and the
implications for intrapsychic and intrafamilial rela-
tions (which finds broader though not unanimous
support), Le
A concept assumed in the Victorian period to be
central to the religions of supposedly less evolved
societies, the term taboo today generally is used to
refer to prohibitions grounded in custom or religion
rather than in bureaucratic law or common sense and
hence bearing some moral weight. Taboos can be
widespread, observed over the long term, internalized,
and deeply felt, as in the case of incest taboos, or
applied temporarily with respect to specific persons,
acts, conditions, and objects. This article reviews the
history of the concept which can be seen to reflect
the development of anthropological theory more
generally.
vi-Strauss argued that the incest taboo
forms the logical basis of society and is rooted in the
universal mental capacity to make categorical binary
distinctions, notably those between self and other,
culture and nature. In an ambitious attempt to unify
and critique the theory, Rubin added the injunction
against homosexual relations.
It is Le
1. Taboos, Social Order, and Moral Persons
The word taboo is originally Polynesian. Via the
writings of explorers like Cook and missionaries like
Ellis it rapidly entered ordinary usage in Victorian
England. In 1842 the 7th edition of the
Encyclopaedia
Britannica
defined taboo succinctly as, ‘A word used
by the South Sea islanders, and nearly of the same
import as prohibited or interdicted. It applies equally
to persons and things, and is also expressive of
anything sacred, devoted, or eminent’ (quoted in
Steiner 1999, p. 164). In the hands of Robertson
Smith and Frazer, taboo came to epitomize the es-
sence of primitive thought, distinguishing it from
civilized religion (i.e., the Judaeo–Christian tradition)
in the way it combined holiness with defilement. In a
deconstructive work equivalent to that which Le
vi-Strauss’s emphasis on classification that
has most influenced subsequent analyses of taboos
and has proved fruitful in understanding their varied
and often ostensibly trivial content. Drawing on their
common heritage of Durkheim, both Douglas and
Leach emphasized the role of taboos in protecting
systems of social classification by banning anomalous
or marginal words, objects, and practices that might
violate the order of the categories or blur their
distinctions. The title of Douglas’s major work,
Purity
and Danger
(1966), captures the crux of her argument
perfectly. Dirt, or that which is viewed with revulsion
and hence tabooed, is ‘matter out of place’ and hence
always relative to a system of classification but also
dangerous for it. Building on Steiner, Douglas argued
convincingly that individual taboos can only be
understood as parts of larger social wholes; that taboos
are not false or failed attempts at science; that Western
lives are replete with taboos which are no more or less
rational than those of other societies; and that without
principles of restriction, conceptual and moral dis-
crimination would be compromised and the ensuing
freedom of both thought and action would be hope-
lessly chaotic.
Douglas’s argument has inspired much subsequent
work, especially on gender, the body, and food.
Among the merits of her approach is the ability to
show structural similarities in taboos, whatever their
specific content, both within a given society, between
societies, and across both ostensibly secular (e.g.,
hygiene, courtesy) and sacred realms. Somewhat more
controversial have been attempts both to illustrate
how taboos in various orders of phenomena (notably
vi-
Strauss performed for totemism, Steiner admirably
summarized and critiqued the use of the term through
the first half of the twentieth century, demonstrating
the problems with applying a culturally particular
concept in a comparative and evolutionary fashion.
Steiner showed that it was impossible to separate
defilement from the sacred in any consistent manner.
Steiner’s critique of the abstraction and reification of
taboo has been pursued by MacIntyre, while his
insights into its significance in Polynesia have been
considerably enlarged by Gell, Sahlins, and Valeri.
The most profound reflections on taboo have
concerned its universal social basis. Both Freud and
Le
vi-Strauss have seen the incest taboo as fundamental
to the constitution of society. For Freud, internalizing
prohibitions against intra-familial violence and sexual
15429
relations establishes the conditions for the emergence
of kinship and moral conscience. Le
Taboo
vi-Strauss
demonstrated that specific positive rules of mar-
riage—made possible by the underlying incest
taboo—generate certain patterns of relationship over
time. Taboos, by contrast, in that they do not specify
what must or should be done, allow greater degrees of
freedom. Yet, as Fortes argued, they are also grasped
more easily and internalized more deeply than positive
injunctions.
While taboos usually are analyzed as discursive
elements, it is important to understand that they
become realized in practice. Often the most con-
sequential taboos are the least explicit. If in a structural
model the semantic contents of taboos distinguish
who or what one is not, from a practice perspective it
is the observance of the taboo that substantiates who
one is. Van Gennep saw taboos as acts of obligation,
creating both continuity and separation. Fortes em-
phasized the morally binding quality of taboos and the
personal significance of observing them for the inter-
nalization of an enduring identity and the acknow-
ledgment of dependence on, and obligation to, higher
authorities or values. Moreover, taboos ‘crystallize
these abstract norms in concrete objects and precise
rules of conduct which are the more effective because
they are of no utilitarian or rational value’ (Fortes
1987, p. 129).
Fortes observed both the essentially inward orien-
tation of taboos, especially with respect to eating, and
their continuous nature. An important consequence of
the fact that taboos are phrased in the negative is that
their observance is a relatively continuous and private
form of action, whereas carrying out a positive order is
a discontinuous and relatively discrete and public act.
Hence while the power entailed in observing a taboo
may be less explicit and forthright than a direct
command, the implications may be more profound.
Defiance of taboo may challenge subjection, identity,
and value at quite a deep level.
Taboos, then, are not merely imposed, lifted, or
carried out in discrete acts but observed continuously.
As practical disposition the observance of taboos
exemplifies Mauss’s and Bourdieu’s notion of the
habitus and Aristotelian virtue that underlies it.
Although not always accepted happily, taboos index
personal dignity and (self-)respect, and insofar as they
are embodied statements, they may be understood as
acts which performatively establish and maintain
moral states of social commitment and individual
conscience. Moreover, in the visceral reactions to the
violation of taboos (nausea, disgust, etc.), underlying
social conventions are naturalized. Hence, as Douglas
also intuits, taboos do not merely signify social or
cosmological order but, in acts of separation, com-
mitment, and principled refusal, they constitute it.
Taboos may be understood phenomenologically
with respect to a dialectic of subject and object. Gell
argues that it is through taboos, applied at varying
levels of specificity across social categories, and oper-
ating as intentional, if negative, engagement with the
world, that the ego or self is constituted. ‘To observe a
taboo is to establish an identifiable self by establishing
a relationship (negative in this case—
not
eating) with
an external reality such that the ‘‘self’’ only comes into
existence in and through this relationship’ (1979,
p. 136). ‘Taboos on eating, on killing, on sexual in-
tercourse, on looking at, touching, etc., together
circumscribe a ‘‘hole’’ in the texture of shareable
intersubjective reality which, privileged with respect to
a specific individual, constitutes his soul, or ego, or
personality. Taboo does more than express the self: it
constitutes the self’ (1979, p. 137). When Gell’s ar-
gument that taboos carve out the self is combined with
Le
vi-Strauss’ argument that taboos generate exchange
and hence society, it is clear that the self is relationally
constituted, simultaneously held apart from and con-
nected to others, simultaneously social and itself.
There is a dynamic quality here: Umeda of Papua New
Guinea alternate phases of taboo and consumption; in
Gell’s analysis the taboo phase restores the integrity of
the ego by ‘reconstituting it as a closed system’ (1979,
p. 146). Elsewhere Gell (1995) generalizes the logic of
taboo in its original Polynesian locus where it pro-
duced differentiation in a cosmos in which sacredness
was immanent rather than transcendental.
2. Transgression
One of Freud’s central arguments concerned the
essential ambivalence of taboos, understood as the
coalescence of the conflict between a desire and its
refusal, attraction, and repression. It is clear that
anticipation or suspicion of the violation of taboos
often produces visceral reactions—whether laughter,
lust, or queasiness—disgust rather than mere indig-
15430
diet) reflect concerns with the maintenance of social
boundaries and divisions and, at a greater level of
abstraction, to plot the degree of general interest in
maintaining the purity of classificatory orders against
the underlying nature of the social relations (the type
of society, relatively defined). Following one strain of
Durkheim’s thought, Douglas gives primacy to the
form and integration of social groupings and thus,
despite her radical demonstration of the contingent
nature of particular taboos, the argument appears
rather conservative. Purity and impurity are not only
relative to a system of categories, but this system may
also be arranged with respect to a hierarchy of sanctity
within a holistic universe, as epitomized by Dumont’s
account of the South Asian caste system. Ensuing
questions about the relationship of sanctity and
encompassment to power have been much debated.
While the presence of taboos is universal, their
substance and direction are not, giving rise to cul-
turally specific social orders. In some parts of the
world, like eastern Indonesia, prescriptive rules are
emphasized, while in others, like Madagascar, pros-
criptions are pervasive (Lambek 1992). Le
Tacit Knowledge, Psychology of
nation. Moreover, because the embodied practice of
powerful taboos goes without saying, their pervasive
presence is only highlighted by the observance of
violation. That is to say, taboos are often indicated
through instances of their transgression, in effect, a
double negation. As Douglas, Gluckman, and Turner
showed, suitably framed transgressions may provide
central episodes in religious experience, moral edu-
cation, and social transition, but otherwise they are
perceived as highly threatening. Transgressions may
establish political dissent or domination, but they are
also the source and substance of neurotic illness, social
panic, and much fantasy.
Stallybrass and White (1986) conjoined these ideas
with Bakhtin’s notion of the carnivalesque and Elias’s
history of manners to explore the significance of
taboos in the historical constitution of the European
middle class. The rigorous expulsion of what was
perceived as disorderly, low, and carnal has produced,
in their view, various ‘returns of the repressed.’ These
include nostalgia, longing, fascination, and even the
academic preoccupation with the body.
While some people continue to argue for a biological
basis to the incest taboo (and possibly certain other
widespread prohibitions), the increased acknowledg-
ment of the prevalence of actual incestuous relations
supports those theories that find the source of taboos
in culture or society and human ambivalence. Indeed,
the question has been raised whether incest taboos are
any longer necessary and whether they have been
de
facto
lifted, or at least limited. On another front, the
violence and rape characteristic of twentieth-century
warfare, and the torture carried out by repressive
political regimes, must be recognized. Indeed, these
might be viewed as deliberate and state-sanctioned
liftings of taboos in order to maximize personal
violation. However, due in part to fears of contami-
nation that accompany any discussion of trans-
gression, research has focussed more on the condition
of victims than the acts of perpetration.
Of course, the presence of taboos has always
generated fantasies of transgression. These are often
di
cult to distinguish from actual transgressions and
at the same time may produce transgressive acts of
their own, as in the ‘de-repression’ characteristic of
accusations of witchcraft and child abuse prevalent in
recent years in North America and northern Europe
but also globally (Comaroff 1997, LaFontaine 1998).
The need for moral discernment is not always matched
by epistemological clarity, yet the fantasies and acts,
characteristic of sites and moments of moral vertigo
and vacuum, underline the near universality of disgust
in the face of certain kinds of physical and sexual
brutality and invasiveness, the universal need for
avenues for the exercise of dignified moral agency, and
the place of taboos among such means.
Conversely, it could be argued that the preceding
discussion suffers from an overly socialized, moralistic,
and tame conception of taboos; that negation and
excess are central to religious experience; and that
transgression be recognized as ‘the ultimate sacred act’
(Taussig 1998, p. 361).
1966 Totem and taboo. In: Goody J (ed.)
Religion, Morality, and the Person
. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, UK
Freud S 1958
Totem and Taboo
. Vol. 13 of The Standard Edition
of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud
(Strachey J, ed. and trans.). Hogarth, London
Gell A 1979 Reflections on a cut finger: Taboo in the Umeda
Conception of the Self. In: Hook R H (ed.)
Fantasy and
Symbol
. Academic Press, London
Gell A 1995 Closure and multiplication: An essay on Polynesian
cosmology and ritual. In: de Coppet D, Iteanu A (eds.)
Cosmos and Society in Oceania
. Berg, Oxford, UK
LaFontaine J S 1998
Speak of the De
il
. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, UK
Lambek M 1992 Taboo as cultural practice among Malagasy
speakers.
Man
27
(2): 245–66
Leach E 1964 Anthropological aspects of language: Animal
categories and verbal abuse. In: Lenneberg E H (ed.)
New
Directions in the Study of Language
. MIT Press, Cambridge,
MA
Le
, 1st
edn. Presses Universitaires de France, Paris (1966
The
Elementary Structures of Kinship
. Beacon, Boston)
MacIntyre A 1990
Three Ri
le
mentaires de la parente
al Versions of Moral Enquiry
.
Duckworth, London
Rubin G 1975 The trac in women: Notes on the ‘Political
Economy’ of sex. In: Reiter R R (ed.)
Toward an Anthropology
of Women
. Monthly Review Press, New York
Stallybrass P, White A 1986
The Politics and Poetics of
Transgression
. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY
Steiner F 1999
1956 Taboo. In: Adler J, Fardon R (eds.)
Taboo,
Truth, and Religion: Franz Baermann Steiner Selected Writ-
ings
, Vol. I. Berghahn, New York
Taussig M 1998 Transgression. In: Taylor M C (ed.)
Critical
Terms for Religious Studies
. University of Chicago Press,
Chicago
Van Gennep A 1904
Tabou et tote
misme a
Madagascar
. Ernest
Leroux, Paris
M. Lambek
Tacit Knowledge, Psychology of
Tacit comes from the Latin
tacitus
and translates
roughly as
silent
,or
unspoken
and, indeed, the sense of
the unverbalized, the unuttered, is still carried by
contemporary usage. Usually the Hungarian
British
15431
Bibliography
Comaroff J 1997 Consuming passions: Child abuse, fetishism,
and the ‘New World Order’.
Culture
17
: 7–19
Douglas M 1966
Purity and Danger
. Routledge & Kegan Paul,
London
Dumont L 1967
Homo Hierarchicus
. Gallimard, Paris (1970
University of Chicago Press, Chicago)
Fortes M 1987
vi-Strauss C 1949
Les structures e
Tacit Knowledge, Psychology of
scholar Michael Polanyi is credited with importing the
notion of tacit knowledge into the social sciences and
the credit is deservedly his (Polanyi 1962, 1966, Reber
1993a). In Polanyi’s framework, tacit knowledge was
information that was intensely personal, intro-
spectively opaque, and communicatively unrespon-
sive. It was also, importantly, complex knowledge,
abstract in nature, and deeply causal. He wrote of
knowing more about familiar conceptual domains
than we can tell and characterized his own early life as
a creative scientist as being largely a struggle to make
tacit knowledge available to consciousness and open
to introspection and communication.
Within psychology, this notion of a rich, personal
knowledge base with direct causal links to behavior
has been around for a long time, surfacing and
resurfacing in various forums from the psychoanalytic
to the neurocognitive, from the study of perception
and learning to models of memory and information
storage. The flurry of interest in these issues has
spawned a host of synonyms, so much so that Polyani’s
original term
tacit
is actually rather rare. Preferred
lexical entries refer to knowledge that is
implicit
or
unconscious
, occasionally to mental processes that are
nonconscious
,
unaware
,
procedural
,
co
an exclusionary clause is invoked, the tacit dimension
includes only those processes and mechanisms that
operate while remaining more or less impenetrable to
top-down, conscious access and control.
As noted above, the cover term
tacit knowledge
,
despite its currency in earlier work and its central
position in Polanyi’s writings, no longer appears in
many ‘keyword’ lists. This is too bad. One of the
di
culties with much recent work on the cognitive
unconscious is that connotatively loaded terms such as
awareness
and
consciousness
pepper the field and fuel
disputes that are often unproductive and unsatisfying.
In the following, synonyms will be freely interchanged
and attempts will be made to resurrect the core term
tacit
. So, with lexicographic inclusiveness in place, the
following are the four primary areas of research.
1. The Four Primary Areas of Research
ert
, and, from
time to time, to functions which are
incidental
or
automatic
. However, no matter what cover term is
employed, the focus remains on the cluster of per-
ceptual and cognitive processes that function largely
independently of awareness of both the processes by
which such knowledge was acquired and of the mental
representations that result from such learning. In
short,
tacit knowledge
, by whatever name enjoys
momentary currency, is knowledge that is acquired
and used with little in the way of the top-down,
modulating control of consciousness. And herein lie
the big psychological puzzles. How is complex knowl-
edge acquired largely outside of consciousness? How
are memories encoded so that their impact on behavior
is manifested by indirect measures while their contents
remain largely unavailable to recall and recognition?
Is the tacit system merely functionally distinguishable
from the more cognitively familiar, consciously modu-
lated systems? Or, as many suspect, are the observed
dissociations reflective of deeper neurocognitive
systems? Is it possible that explicit, retrievable knowl-
edge systems are linked with biological systems that
are evolutionarily distinct from the tacit, implicit
systems? Is knowledge that was acquired implicitly
superficial knowledge that is tied to the specific form
of the stimulus displays, or can such knowledge also be
abstract and symbolic?
While work on these questions since the 1970s has
touched on virtually every area in modern psychology,
it is not unreasonable to distill it down to four classical
problems. Not surprisingly, these four are the classical
topics that have dominated psychological thought
since the nineteenth century: perception, learning,
memory, and motivation. The difference is that here
1.1 Tacit or Implicit Perception
For the most part, the existence of information pick-
up that occurs when the stimulus materials are
presented under nonoptimal conditions is a generally
accepted phenomenon. The last serious critique of the
effect (Holender 1986) was countered by a large
number of effective rebuttals and it seems safe to
conclude that the acquisition of information about
stimulus displays that participants are unaware of
perceiving is a robust phenomenon. There is also good
evidence that such subliminally perceived represen-
tations have emotive elements (Kunst-Wilson and
Zajonc 1980). For more detail on this issue, see
Perception without Awareness, Psychology of
.
1.2 Implicit or Tacit Memory
Implicitly held memories are, in effect, those memorial
residues of experience whose contents affect behavior
while remaining largely unavailable for recall or
recognition. Such memories show up primarily in
indirect tests such as word-stem completion tasks (fill
in the blank with the first word that comes to mind:
MOT
Psychology of
.
e
1.3 Implicit or Tacit Learning
Implicit learning is the process whereby knowledge
about complex stimulus domains is acquired largely
15432
) where participants reliably complete the task
using items previously encountered even though they
are unable consciously to recall them. One of the more
intriguing findings is that implicit memory is relatively
intact in amnesic patients who manifest severely
disordered explicit memories. For additional infor-
mation on this issue, see
Implicit Memory, Cogniti
Tacit Knowledge, Psychology of
without involvement of top-down, conscious control
(Reber 1993b). Naturally occurring examples of the
operation of implicit learning are language acquisition
and the process of socialization. Implicit learning
yields implicit or tacit knowledge in that not only is the
learner unaware of the process of learning, the very
knowledge itself is highly resistant to explication.
This notion that deep, abstract knowledge about a
complex stimulus domain can be acquired and repre-
sented outside of consciousness is the one that is
closest to Polanyi’s original use of the term. In
Polanyi’s framework, tacit, personal knowledge
played a critical role in everyday life. Moreover, such
communicatively resistant knowledge was also viewed
as lying at the very core of creativity. In Polyani’s
epistemology, to engage in a creative act to struggle to
make tacitly acquired and held knowledge conscious
and communicable. Doing science, in his mind, was
following the urging of one’s carefully crafted
intuitions and slowly shaping the reservoir of initially
unavailable, tacit knowledge out into a communicable
form.
tacit dimension appear to hinge on the notion that
the unconscious, as Polanyi maintained, is just flat-out
smart. Specifically, we can consider the following.
2.1 Methodological
It has been argued that the observed implicit–explicit
distinction is not an ontological one but merely results
from the procedures used to measure participants’
awareness of held knowledge (Holender 1986, Shanks
and St. John 1994). This argument turns on two
points: first, that the measures used to evaluate tacit
knowledge are more sensitive than those used to
evaluate consciously held knowledge, and second, that
no other independent evidence exists to support the
distinction. There are good reasons for suspecting that
the former is (or was) correct. When more effective
methods of inquiry are employed, participants often
have shown more awareness of held knowledge than
first suspected. Contemporary researchers are much
more careful to use more sensitive measures of
knowledge held by participants in these studies. The
argument, however, appears weaker on the second
point. There is a large and growing body of evidence
that shows that distinct neuroanatomical substrata are
involved in the acquisition and storage of tacit
knowledge, specifically structures in the medial tem-
poral lobes. Patients with severe damage in these
cortical regions show often devastating episodic mem-
ory dysfunctions with little or no disruption in the
pick-up and acquisition of tacit knowledge. In ad-
dition, there are good reasons for suspecting that the
two systems have emerged under distinct evolutionary
pressures and have very different evolutionary bio-
logical histories (Sherry and Schacter 1987, Reber
1992).
ation
The focus here is the exploration of unconsciously
held representations. The essential argument, which
derives from the classical, Freudian approach, is that
unconsciously held knowledge plays its primary role
by modifying and adjusting perceptions and mem-
ories. This approach goes one step further than the
above in that the unconsciously held knowledge in
assumed actually to change conscious representations
in accordance with deeply held knowledge systems.
This use is found primarily in analytically and psycho-
dynamically oriented research where unconsciously
held knowledge is presumed to have its impact on
behavior through disguised, hidden routes (e.g.,
Horowitz 1988) although hints of it emerge in more
recent work on the development of preferences and
aesthetic judgment (Manza and Bornstein 1995).
2.2 Functional
The point is often made that there is no ‘true’ cleavage
between tacit knowledge and knowledge held at the
edges of consciousness, that the observed dissociations
are mere functional adjustments made to particular
contexts (Whittlesea and Dorken 1993). The argument
here is that participants in standard experimental
settings shift from conscious to unconscious modes
depending upon the constraints placed upon them and
the contexts in which they are required to function.
Neither system is the default system and, in fact, they
should probably not even be thought of as separate
systems but as poles on a continuum running from the
deeply tacit to the poignantly conscious. From a
functionalists point of view, there is much to rec-
ommend in this contention. In all likelihood, most of
the interesting things that human beings do on a
ersies
Perhaps not surprisingly, many of the issues raised in
these contexts have proven controversial. It is im-
portant to appreciate that most of modern experi-
mental psychology is built on a foundation that goes
back to Locke and other British empiricists. This
approach, which favored introspection as the primary
method of inquiry, equated
mental
with
conscious
and
rejected out of hand the notion of a cognitively
sophisticated unconscious. Although few appreciate
(consciously?) these Lockean roots, many of the
arguments being waged over the characteristics of the
15433
1.4 Implicit or Tacit Moti
2. Disputes and Contro
Plik z chomika:
widez2
Inne pliki z tego folderu:
Elsevier Science International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences Vol. A-B.pdf
(13489 KB)
AMACOM.The.Genomics.Age.How.DNA.Technology.Is.Transforming.the.Way.We.Live.and.Who.We.Are.pdf
(2486 KB)
Elsevier Science International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences Vol. C.pdf
(16482 KB)
Elsevier Science International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences Vol. D-E.pdf
(16131 KB)
Elsevier Science International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences Vol. F-H.pdf
(17383 KB)
Inne foldery tego chomika:
art
Astronomy
Biology
Chemistry
cognitive
Zgłoś jeśli
naruszono regulamin